One of the difficulties in explaining the Socialist attitude to
anarchism is that there are many different varieties of anarchism, some
involving violence, some non-violence; some are anti-religious, some
religious. Some anarchists are influenced by Freud; others by different
schools of psychology. Some favour the setting up of anarchist
communities now, as a transitional step. Others are individualistic,
being mainly unconcerned about society's problems. Most envisage the
abolition of money, yet some are interested in monetary reforms. The
list is endless. Each would have to be examined separately. The best
procedure now would be to take a school of anarchism that appears to be
close to our standpoint and discuss this.
Basically this form of
anarchism envisages the abolition of the state, of buying and selling,
of international trade, of frontiers and the like. Its aim would be a
consciously regulated society where production would be to satisfy human
need; where the workers in particular industries and plants are loosely
associated with others in co-operating federations. The adherents of
this school argue that the only way in which this state of affairs could
be brought about would be by the growth of a majority sufficiently
independent-minded to see the need for this kind of world and to begin
to organise for it. This would mean withdrawing support from all
political activity (parties, voting, etc.) and ultimately destroying the
state and all related institutions, and building the nuclei of the new
society within the old.
Our basic arguments against the anarchist
attitude are these. Any movement concerned with the problems of society
(and of the working class in particular) must have certain unified
theoretical conceptions. It must have a theory embracing coherently the
past and the present, the dynamics of social change, the nature of human
behaviour and so on. Without such a unified theory it is not possible
to take consistent action on a rational basis, or to modify it
meaningfully in the light of experience. We argue that anarchists lack
such a theoretical system. In fact the views of even a limited segment
of anarchists such as that under discussion involve a wide variety of
theories. Such eclecticism preludes the possibility of sound theory and
therefore the possibility of sustained correct action. Of course, we are
not suggesting that one should not examine and re-examine all relevant
theories.
With regard to the attempt to establish a libertarian
society by direct action without the ballot-box a number of points can
be made.
Anarchists, in their criticism, tend to argue that all
"parliamentary" parties, within which they include the Socialist Party
of Great Britain, have in the past, and in the present, betrayed the
working class; that Parliament is not the real seat of power (a
"power-house") but a "talking-shop" or "gas-house"; that the Socialist
Party contests elections, aims at parliamentary majorities and so on;
and that therefore it is and will be no different from all other
parties. Also, the SPGB participates in all the activities which
perpetuate what anarchists see as harmful illusions about law, the state
and parliamentary democracy.
Our reply is that these anarchists
fail to distinguish between the different content of the term
"parliamentary" as applied to orthodox parties and to the Socialist
Party. They do not see, or perhaps do not want to see, that we insist on
the necessity of majority understanding behind Socialist delegates with
a mandate for Socialism, merely using the state and parliament for one
revolutionary act, after which the Socialist Party has no further
existence, subsequent action being the responsibility of society.
We
hold it to be absolutely essential that the transformation to a new
society be started by formal democratic methods—that is, by persuasion
and the secret ballot. For there is no other way of ascertaining
accurately the views of the population. The result of a properly
conducted ballot will make it clear, in the event of an overwhelming
Socialist vote, to any minority that they are the minority and that any
attempt to oppose the desires of the majority by violence would be
futile. An attempt to establish an anarchist society by ignoring the
democratic process thereby gives any recalcitrant minority, possibly
violent, the excuse for anti-libertarian direct action itself. They
could claim that the assumed majority did not in fact exist or that the
assumed majority was not likely to be a consistent or decisive one. In
any event there would be no secure justification for a radical change.
There might well be unnecessary setbacks and disruptions of the
revolutionary movement—possibly involving hardship or loss of life among
the working class.
In general, the denigration in a sweeping
fashion of Parliament and so on makes it easier for authoritarian
movements of all kinds to lay the blame for social problems on
democratic institutions instead of on capitalism—as, for instance, did
the Nazis and so-called Communists in the Weimar Republic.
The
anarchists propose to ignore the state saying, paradoxically, that it
does not reflect real social power and that in the desired
transformation of society its controllers would be corrupted. Socialists
argue that it does reflect real social power and consciousness; that a
majority of society comprising class-conscious Socialists would
effectively control its mandated delegates who, having free access to
things, would have no need of power (individually or as a group).
Finally, the anarchist proposal to ignore the state is short-sighted in
so far as the formal establishment of the Socialist majority's control
of the state does avoid the possibility of effective use of its forces
against the revolutionary movement.
Anarchists also tend to refer
to the regimes in Russia, Eastern Europe and Cuba as Marxist or
Communist, saying that all the antisocial aspects of these systems arise
directly or indirectly as a result of the ideas of Marx. In so doing,
of course, they do a disservice to the truth.
(December 1967)
No comments:
Post a Comment